End (category theory) – Wikipedia

before-content-x4

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

after-content-x4

In category theory, an end of a functor

S:Cop×CX{displaystyle S:mathbf {C} ^{mathrm {op} }times mathbf {C} to mathbf {X} }

is a universal extranatural transformation from an object e of X to S.

More explicitly, this is a pair

(e,ω){displaystyle (e,omega )}

, where e is an object of X and

ω:e¨S{displaystyle omega :e{ddot {to }}S}

is an extranatural transformation such that for every extranatural transformation

β:x¨S{displaystyle beta :x{ddot {to }}S}

there exists a unique morphism

after-content-x4
h:xe{displaystyle h:xto e}


of X with

βa=ωah{displaystyle beta _{a}=omega _{a}circ h}


for every object a of C.

By abuse of language the object e is often called the end of the functor S (forgetting

ω{displaystyle omega }

) and is written

Characterization as limit: If X is complete and C is small, the end can be described as the equalizer in the diagram

where the first morphism being equalized is induced by

S(c,c)S(c,c){displaystyle S(c,c)to S(c,c’)}

and the second is induced by

S(c,c)S(c,c){displaystyle S(c’,c’)to S(c,c’)}

.

The definition of the coend of a functor

S:Cop×CX{displaystyle S:mathbf {C} ^{mathrm {op} }times mathbf {C} to mathbf {X} }

is the dual of the definition of an end.

Thus, a coend of S consists of a pair

(d,ζ){displaystyle (d,zeta )}

, where d is an object of X and

ζ:S¨d{displaystyle zeta :S{ddot {to }}d}


is an extranatural transformation, such that for every extranatural transformation

γ:S¨x{displaystyle gamma :S{ddot {to }}x}

there exists a unique morphism

g:dx{displaystyle g:dto x}

of X with

γa=gζa{displaystyle gamma _{a}=gcirc zeta _{a}}

for every object a of C.

The coend d of the functor S is written

Characterization as colimit: Dually, if X is cocomplete and C is small, then the coend can be described as the coequalizer in the diagram

Examples[edit]

  • Natural transformations:

    Suppose we have functors

    F,G:CX{displaystyle F,G:mathbf {C} to mathbf {X} }

    then

    In this case, the category of sets is complete, so we need only form the equalizer and in this case

    the natural transformations from

    F{displaystyle F}

    to

    G{displaystyle G}

    . Intuitively, a natural transformation from

    F{displaystyle F}

    to

    G{displaystyle G}

    is a morphism from

    F(c){displaystyle F(c)}

    to

    G(c){displaystyle G(c)}

    for every

    c{displaystyle c}

    in the category with compatibility conditions. Looking at the equalizer diagram defining the end makes the equivalence clear.

  • Geometric realizations:

    Let

    T{displaystyle T}

    be a simplicial set. That is,

    T{displaystyle T}

    is a functor

    ΔopSet{displaystyle Delta ^{mathrm {op} }to mathbf {Set} }

    . The discrete topology gives a functor

    SetTop{displaystyle mathbf {Set} to mathbf {Top} }

    , where

    Top{displaystyle mathbf {Top} }

    is the category of topological spaces. Moreover, there is a map

    γ:ΔTop{displaystyle gamma :Delta to mathbf {Top} }

    sending the object

    [n]{displaystyle [n]}

    of

    Δ{displaystyle Delta }

    to the standard

    n{displaystyle n}

    -simplex inside

    Rn+1{displaystyle mathbb {R} ^{n+1}}

    . Finally there is a functor

    Top×TopTop{displaystyle mathbf {Top} times mathbf {Top} to mathbf {Top} }

    that takes the product of two topological spaces.

    Define

    S{displaystyle S}

    to be the composition of this product functor with

    T×γ{displaystyle Ttimes gamma }

    . The coend of

    S{displaystyle S}

    is the geometric realization of

    T{displaystyle T}

    .

References[edit]

  • Mac Lane, Saunders (2013). Categories For the Working Mathematician. Springer Science & Business Media. pp. 222–226.
  • Loregian, Fosco (2015). “This is the (co)end, my only (co)friend”. arXiv:1501.02503 [math.CT].

External links[edit]


after-content-x4