Image (category theory) – Wikipedia
In category theory, a branch of mathematics, the image of a morphism is a generalization of the image of a function.
General definition[edit]
Given a category
and a morphism
in
of
is a monomorphism
satisfying the following universal property:
- There exists a morphism such that .
- For any object with a morphism and a monomorphism such that , there exists a unique morphism such that .
Remarks:
- such a factorization does not necessarily exist.
- is unique by definition of monic.
- , therefore by monic.
- is monic.
- already implies that is unique.

The image of
is often denoted by
or
.
Proposition: If
has all equalizers then the
in the factorization
of (1) is an epimorphism.[2]
Proof
Let
be such that
, one needs to show that
. Since the equalizer of
exists,
factorizes as
with
monic. But then
is a factorization of
with
monomorphism. Hence by the universal property of the image there exists a unique arrow
such that
and since
is monic
. Furthermore, one has
and by the monomorphism property of
one obtains
.

This means that
and thus that
equalizes
, whence
.
Second definition[edit]
In a category
with all finite limits and colimits, the image is defined as the equalizer
of the so-called cokernel pair
.[3]


[clarification needed]
Remarks:
- Finite bicompleteness of the category ensures that pushouts and equalizers exist.
- can be called regular image as is a regular monomorphism, i.e. the equalizer of a pair of morphisms. (Recall also that an equalizer is automatically a monomorphism).
- In an abelian category, the cokernel pair property can be written and the equalizer condition . Moreover, all monomorphisms are regular.
Theorem — If
always factorizes through regular monomorphisms, then the two definitions coincide.
Proof
First definition implies the second: Assume that (1) holds with
regular monomorphism.
- Equalization: one needs to show that . As the cokernel pair of and by previous proposition, since has all equalizers, the arrow in the factorization is an epimorphism, hence .
- Universality: in a category with all colimits (or at least all pushouts) itself admits a cokernel pair

- Moreover, as a regular monomorphism, is the equalizer of a pair of morphisms but we claim here that it is also the equalizer of .
- Indeed, by construction thus the “cokernel pair” diagram for yields a unique morphism such that . Now, a map which equalizes also satisfies , hence by the equalizer diagram for , there exists a unique map such that .
- Finally, use the cokernel pair diagram (of ) with : there exists a unique such that . Therefore, any map which equalizes also equalizes and thus uniquely factorizes as . This exactly means that is the equalizer of .
Second definition implies the first:

- Then so that by the “cokernel pair” diagram (of ), with , there exists a unique such that .
- Now, from (m from the equalizer of (i1, i2) diagram), one obtains , hence by the universality in the (equalizer of (d1, d2) diagram, with f replaced by m), there exists a unique such that .
Examples[edit]
In the category of sets the image of a morphism
is the inclusion from the ordinary image
to
. In many concrete categories such as groups, abelian groups and (left- or right) modules, the image of a morphism is the image of the correspondent morphism in the category of sets.
In any normal category with a zero object and kernels and cokernels for every morphism, the image of a morphism
can be expressed as follows:
- im f = ker coker f
In an abelian category (which is in particular binormal), if f is a monomorphism then f = ker coker f, and so f = im f.
See also[edit]
References[edit]
- ^ Mitchell, Barry (1965), Theory of categories, Pure and applied mathematics, vol. 17, Academic Press, ISBN 978-0-12-499250-4, MR 0202787 Section I.10 p.12
- ^ Mitchell, Barry (1965), Theory of categories, Pure and applied mathematics, vol. 17, Academic Press, ISBN 978-0-12-499250-4, MR 0202787 Proposition 10.1 p.12
- ^ Kashiwara, Masaki; Schapira, Pierre (2006), “Categories and Sheaves”, Grundlehren der Mathematischen Wissenschaften, vol. 332, Berlin Heidelberg: Springer, pp. 113–114 Definition 5.1.1
Recent Comments